josh blog

Ordinary language is all right.

One could divide humanity into two classes:
those who master a metaphor, and those who hold by a formula.
Those with a bent for both are too few, they do not comprise a class.

newest | archives | search | about | wishlist | flickr | email | rss

7 Oct '25 04:17:27 AM

'Whether this contemplative attitude had its origin in my contemplative function as a guardian of culture within society, as a Marxist would state without further ado; or whether it represents a primary object of my existence (and one does find it in pride, freedom, the destabilization of oneself, the contemplative stoicism and the optimism which certainly form part of my primary project)—that's what I do not wish to decide here. It's certain, in any case, that this way of taking refuge at the top of the tower when its base is under attack, and of looking down from above without blenching, albeit with eyes somewhat widened by fear, is the attitude I chose in '38-'39 faced with the threats of war. It's also the one which, a little earlier, inspired my article on the transcendence of the Ego—where I quite simply eject the Self from consciousness, like some nosy visitor. With myself, I didn't have that tender intimacy which causes there to be adhesions (as in medical parlance) between the Self and consciousness—so that if one tried to remove the former, one would be afraid of tearing the latter. It was perfectly all right outside, on the contrary. It remained there, granted; but I watched it through the pane with all the calm and severity in the world.

I long believed, moreover, that the existence of a character couldn't be reconciled with the freedom of consciousness: I thought character was nothing but a bunch of maxims, more moral than psychological, in which our neighbour sums up his experience of us. Consciousness-as-refuge remained, as was propoer, colourless, odourless and tasteless. It was only this year, with the advent of war, that I understood the truth: character assuredly must not be confused with all those recipe-maxims of the moralists—'he's quick-tempered; he's lazy; etc.'—but is the primary, free project of our being in the world. I tried to show this for William II.

In short, the existence of a consciousness-as-refuge allowed me to decide at will on how much seriousness to attribute to the situation. I was like someone who, amid the direst adventures, scarcely feels the threatening reality of the tortures being reserved for him—because he always carries with him a pellet of a deadly poison, which will deliver him before anyone can lay a finger on him. There's a character called Katow in La Condition humaine who's like that. So he's great only when he gives his poison to his comrades. It seems to me at that moment he's truly human reality, because nothing holds him outside the world: he's fully inside it, free and without any defence. The passage from absolute freedom to disarmed and human freedom—the rejection of the poison—has taken place this year, and as a direct result I now see my destiny as finite. And my new apprenticeship must consist, precisely, in feeling myself 'in on it': without any defence. It's the war and Heidegger which put me on the right path—Heidegger by showing me there was nothing beyond the project whereby human reality realized itself. Does that mean I'm going to allow the Self back in? No, certainly not. But though the ipseity or totality of the for-itself is not the Self, it's nevertheless the person. I'm in the course of learning, basically, to be a person.

But that's not the aim of my present remarks. I wished simply to indicate that—not having been directly involved in things; not having felt responsible; not having had money worries—I've never taken the world seriously. In other times that could have led me to mysticism, since those whom 'diminished reality' fails to satisfy are only too ready to seek surreality. (And I imagine that fifteen years ago, it was the origin of the surrealist faith for many people—though not all: the influence of the war, which is often mentioned, seems to me far more decisive for the leaders.) But I was an atheist out of pride. Not out of a feeling of pride, but my very existence was pride: I was pride. There was no place for God beside me: I was so perpetually the source of myself that I didn't see what part an Almighty could play in it at all. Subsequently, the wretched poverty of religious thought reinforced my atheism for good. Faith is stupid or it's bad faith. My mother must have grasped something of that frivolous coldness toward the world, for she's fond of repeating that a few centuries earlier I should have become a monk.

Lacking faith, I confined myself to shedding seriousness. There's seriousness, basically, when one starts off from the world or attributes more reality to the world than to oneself. Or, at the very least, when one confers a reality upon oneself insofar as one belongs to the world. It's by no means accidental that materialism is serious; nor is it accidental that it is always and everywhere found as the chosen philosophical doctrine of the revolutionary. For revolutionaries are serious: they first know themselves because they're crushed by the world; they know themselves by virtue of that world which crushes them; and they want to change the world. In this, they find themselves in agreement with their old adversaries, the owners of property, who also know and value themselves by virtue of their situation in the world.

I hate seriousness. Through an engineer's serious concern there passes the whole world—with its inertia, its laws, its stubborn opacity. All serious thought is thickened by the world and coagulates: it's a resignation by man in favour of the world. See that man who shakes his head, saying: 'It's bad! It's very bad!', and try to understand what he puts into that head-shaking. It's this: that the world dominates man; that there were laws and rules to observe—all outside us, stratified, petrified—which would have given a favourable outcome; but those rules have been violated, the catastrophe has arrived and behold man without any recourse. For he no longer has any recourse in himself: he's 'of the world', the world has installed itself within him, and that violated taboo is violated also within him.

One is serious when one doesn't even envisage the possibility of leaving the world. When the world—with its alps and its rocks, its crusts and its oozes, its peatbogs and its deserts: all those obstinate immensities—holds one fast on every side. When one gives oneself the same type of existence as the rock: solidity, inertia, opacity. A serious man is a coagulated consciousness. One is serious when one denies mind. Those unbelievers Plato speaks of in the Sophist, who believe only in what they touch—they're ancestors of the spirit of seriousness. It goes without saying that the serious man, being of the world, doesn't have the least consciousness of his freedom; or rather, if he does have consciousness of it, in terror he buries it deep within him, like some filth. Like the rock, like the atom or like the star, he's determined. And if the spirit of seriousness is characterized by the application with which it considers the consequences of its acts, that's because, for it, all is consequence.

The serious man himself is merely a consequence—an unbearable consequence—never a principle. He's caught for all time in a serious of consequences, and sees only consequences without end. That's why money—sign of all the things in the world; consequence and of consequence—is the object par excellence of seriousness. In short, Marx posited the first dogma of seriousness when he asserted the priority of the object over the subject. And man is serious when he forgets himself; when he makes the subject into an object; when he takes himself for a radiation derived from the world: engineers, doctors, physicists, biologists are serious.

Well, I was protected against seriousness by what I've said. Too much so, rather than not enough. I wasn't of the world, because I was free and first beginning. It's not possible to grasp oneself as consciousness, without thinking that life is a game.

For what is a game, after all, but an activity of which man is the first origin: whose principles man himself ordains and which can have consequences only according to the principles ordained. But as soon as man grasps himself as free, and wishes to use his freedom, all his activity is a game: he's its first principle; he escapes the world by his nature; he himself ordains the value and rules of his acts, and agrees to pay up only according to the rules he himself has ordained and defined. Whence the diminished reality of the world and the disappearance of seriousness.

I have never wished to be serious—I felt too free. At the time of my love-affair with Toulouse, I wrote a long poem—extremely bad I imagine—entitled Peter Pan: song of the little boy who doesn't want to grow up. Always those 'little boys' and those 'little girls'—those clichés of our amorous relations! On the part of a sturdy fellow of twenty and a strapping girl of twenty-three, I find that as incestuous as Rousseau sighing out 'Mother!' all those times to Mme de Warens. But that's not my subject. In any case, that little boy didn't want to grow up for fear of becoming too serious. I could have set my mind at rest: I'm fourteen years older today and I've never been serious—except once, within the walls of the cemetery at Tetuán, because the Beaver wanted to make me put my straw hat on and I didn't want to. I've always claimed responsibility for my acts with the feeling of escaping them entirely by some other route. Because of consciousness's tower, into which I could ascend at will.

But the question which interests me today is the following: is authenticity, by walling up the door to the tower for ever more, going to reinstil in me the spirit of seriousness? I think there can be only one reply: No, by no means! For to grasp oneself as a person is quite the opposite of grasping oneself in terms of the world. And however authentic one is, one's still free—even freer than in the hypothesis of the tower—since one's condemned to a freedom without shadow and without excuse. And, after all, being-in-the-world isn't being of the world. It's even the opposite. Renouncing the ivory tower, I should like the world to appear to me in its full, threatening reality—but I do not, therefore, want my life to stop being a game. That's why I subscribe whole-heartedly to Schiller's phrase: 'Man is fully a man only when he plays.''

26 Sep '25 06:25:45 PM

'I thought I knew something about narrative, but I didn't.'

21 Sep '25 09:23:26 PM

'It's just about playing music—get what's in here, and what's in here, goes through this, to that.'

21 Sep '25 12:35:37 AM

'Call it what you want, but try to get out of it.'

17 Sep '25 05:45:16 PM

'I know when the year is over, I'm going to be curious again.'

17 Sep '25 04:07:34 PM

'… the point is not to tell students what to think, but rather to create the occasion for their free thinking.'

12 Sep '25 10:41:27 PM

(On a tendency toward depersonalization in moral thought to which Hume contributed?)

12 Sep '25 01:20:01 AM

'… keep it like a secret.'

10 Sep '25 08:33:14 PM

Ceaseless Imaginative Striving